Cannabis Indica

The beginning of Philebus in the oldest surviving medieval manuscript, the Codex Clarkianus written in 895 (Oxford, Bodleian Library, Clarke 39)

The Philebus (Φίληβος, Phílēbos) is a work by the ancient Greek philosopher Plato, written in dialogue form. It presents a fictional conversation between Plato's teacher Socrates and two young Athenians, Philebus and Protarchus. The main topic is the ethical evaluation of pleasure.

Philebus and Protarchus are hedonists; they consider pleasure as the highest good and equate it with the absolute Good. Socrates represents the opposing view, prioritizing reason and insight. While he does not dispute the legitimacy and value of pleasure, he points out the diversity of pleasures and argues for a more nuanced assessment. He rejects some forms of pleasure as harmful and assigns a subordinate rank in the hierarchical value order to the remaining "pure" pleasures. The distinction between types of pleasure leads to general considerations about the unity and plurality of types that are subsumed under a generic term, and about the categories into which all being can be divided. Socrates explores the causes, origins, and characteristics of various forms and mixtures of pleasure and pain that occur in human life and their changing combinations, which result in diverse emotional states. The specifics of each form of pleasure are analyzed, and the reasons for their varying evaluations are explained. At the end of the dialogue, Socrates presents a universal value order. In this, proper measure, proportionality, takes the highest place, and pleasure – as far as it is justified – takes the lowest. Harmful pleasures are to be avoided. The right mixture of desired factors is supposed to enable a successful life and bring about a balanced emotional state. Protarchus agrees, while Philebus no longer comments.

The Philebus is considered one of Plato's most challenging dialogues. Manuscripts of the work give it the subtitle "peri hēdonēs, ēthikos" ("ethics/moral concerning pleasure") implying that its topic is "concerning pleasure" and it is a work on ethics — that is, the question of what way of life is best. However, in addition to the core theme of pleasure, it discusses a range of other philosophical questions; "there are large parts in the dialogue that deal with dialectics and ontology but have nothing to do with pleasure and ethics, or if so, only indirectly".[1] In modern research, the classification of all being into four classes by Socrates and the relationship of this classification to Plato's Theory of Forms and to his "unwritten doctrines" recieve particular focus.

Composition[edit]

Research is almost unanimous in classifying Philebus among Plato's "late" dialogues. It has been proposed that the work was composed between 360 and 347 BC, and that it is among the last of the late dialogues of Plato, The dialogue is generally considered to contain less humor than earlier dialogues, and to emphasize philosophy and speculation over drama and poetry.[2][3] This is supported both by statistical linguistic evidence and the content's similarity to other late works, especially the Timaeus. However, the prominent role of the character Socrates in this late work is atypical; many of the other "late" dialogues do not figure Socrates as the main speaking character.[4] Some prefer a slightly earlier dating – originating in the last phase of Plato's middle period. For a more precise placement within the group of late dialogues, there is a lack of sufficient evidence.[5] The hypothesis that Philebus was Plato's response to the hedonism of Eudoxus of Knidus has led to the suggestion that the composition dates soon after 360 BC, though this is highly uncertain.[6]

The textual transmission of Philebus is more problematic than that of other dialogues due to some corruptions, posing special challenges for textual criticism.[7] The oldest surviving medieval manuscript of Philebus was produced in the year 895 in the Byzantine Empire for Arethas of Caesarea, [8] while older manuscripts are limited to a few small papyrus fragments.[9]

Place, time, and participants[edit]

Socrates (Roman bust, 1st century, Louvre, Paris)

Unlike many other Platonic dialogues such as the Phaedo or the Theaetetus, Philebus is not structured as a reported narrative from someone who had heard the conversation, rather, the dialogue begins abruptly, without any framing action. Nothing is revealed about the place, time, and occasion of the conversation. Athens, the hometown of Socrates, is the only possible setting. In addition to the three interlocutors Socrates, Protarchus, and Philebus, a group of young men is also present, who only listen silently. They are apparently admirers of Philebus, whose beauty is valued in the homoerotic milieu.[10] Although the dialogue is named after him, Philebus plays only a minor role. The debate takes place between Socrates and Protarchus.

Socrates, as in most Platonic dialogues, is the main character, the knowledgeable philosopher who leads and dominates the debate and helps the others gain insights. Unlike in the early dialogues, where he holds back his own opinion and leads his interlocutors to new thoughts with purposeful questions, here he develops his own theory. Since the dialogue is a fictional literary construct, the concept that Plato puts in Socrates' mouth should not necessarily be regarded as the position of the historical Socrates, although some scholars[who?] have noted that the ethical attitude of the dialogue character roughly corresponds to that of his real-life model.[11]

Philebus is young, more a teenager than a young man.[12] There is no evidence outside the dialogue for the existence of a historical acquaintance of Socrates named Philebus. It is quite possible that he is a purely fictional character. This is suggested by the fact that no historical bearer of this name is known, and it is a nickname that fits the character ("youth lover" or "friend of youthful pleasure"). Further indicators of fictionality are that the name of his father is not mentioned, and Plato has not given him a profile that would allow for historical classification.[13] It is notable that Philebus, while being the title character and putting forward the initial thesis, leaves the defense of the thesis to Protarchus, while he himself rests and listens.[14] He rarely speaks, and at the end, he silently accepts the refutation of his thesis. He is lazy, interested only in enjoyment, and shies away from the mental effort of a debate. His worldview is simple. His appearance and entire demeanor match the negative image of an incompetent, self-satisfied, and unteachable hedonist that the author wants to present to the reader. It is possible that Plato attributed features of the mathematician and philosopher Eudoxus of Cnidus to him. Eudoxus, a younger contemporary of Plato, was a hedonist, and the critique of hedonism in Philebus was, according to a research hypothesis, directed against his doctrine. However, Plato's Philebus shows less intelligence and interest in intellectual exchange than one would expect from a capable scientist like Eudoxus.[15] His beauty is repeatedly emphasized.[16] His special relationship with the goddess of love Aphrodite, to whom he gives the name of pleasure (Hedone), apparently reflects his view that his commitment to hedonism is in line with the goddess.[17] The fact that Philebus does not participate in the philosophical investigation suggests that he embodies an irrational principle that does not give an account of itself.[18]

Protarchus is considered more likely to be a historical person than Philebus, though doubts still exist.[19] In the dialogue, Socrates calls him "son of Callias".[20] Whether this refers to the wealthy Athenian known in the scholarly literature as "Callias III" is debated.[21] Dorothea Frede believes that Protarchus was one of the two sons of Callias III mentioned in Plato's Apology.[22] They were, according to Plato's statements there, taught by the Sophist Euenus of Paros. In Philebus, Protarchus speaks respectfully of the famous rhetoric teacher Gorgias and identifies himself as his eager student.[23] It is possible that Plato's Protarchus is identifiable with an author – apparently a Rhetorician – of the same name cited by Aristotle.[24]

As a dialogue character, Protarchus, like Philebus, represents the Athenian upper class, in which educational efforts were valued and philosophical topics sparked interest during the time of Socrates. In contrast to Philebus, Protarchus proves to be willing to learn and flexible. He is modest and open to subjecting his hedonistic worldview to an unbiased examination, whereas Philebus declares from the beginning that he will not change his opinion. Eventually, Protarchus is convinced by Socrates, after having tried to defend his position for some time.[25]

Content[edit]

Philebus is considered challenging and difficult to understand. As early as 1809, the influential Plato translator Friedrich Schleiermacher noted in the introduction to the first edition of his translation of the dialogue: “This conversation has always been considered one of the most important, but also one of the hardest among the works of Plato.”[26] However, recent research has emphasized that the structure of Philebus is well thought out.[27] Among other things, the doctrine of affect and the approach to a theory of the comic, which represents the first documented attempt of this kind, are appreciated.[28]

Developing the preconditions[edit]

Initial situation[edit]

The representation starts abruptly in an ongoing conversation. Philebus has posited that pleasure or delight (hēdonḗ) is the good and desirable for all living beings. Pleasure leads to the state of Eudaimonia ("happiness") and thus brings about a successful life. Socrates has disputed this and argued for the counter-thesis that there are more important and advantageous things: reason, knowledge, and memory, a correct understanding, and truthful deliberation. In trying to deal with this, Philebus has become tired. Weary, he now leaves it to Protarchus to defend their common standpoint against Socrates' critique. Protarchus wishes to discuss the matter with an open outcome, whereas Philebus outright states that he will always hold on to the precedence of pleasure.[29]

Pleasure and pleasures[edit]

Socrates begins his critique of the glorification of pleasure by noting that pleasure is not a simple, uniform entity. Rather, there are diverse and even disparate phenomena that are grouped under this term. The pleasure of a profligate person is not comparable to that of a prudent one, and the pleasure of a reasonable person is not comparable to that of a fool. Protarchus counters that although the causes of pleasant feelings are opposing situations, the effect is always the same. He argues that pleasure is always just pleasure and always good. Socrates makes a comparison with the concept of "color": both black and white are colors, yet one is the exact opposite of the other. Similarly, there are opposing pleasures; some are bad, others good. Protarchus initially does not concede this. Only when Socrates also describes his favored good, knowledge, as diverse, does Protarchus admit to the variety of pleasures, as his position is not disadvantaged by this view.[30]

Unity and multiplicity[edit]

The general problem that the conversationalists have encountered is the relationship between unity and multiplicity, one of the core themes of Platonic philosophy. It questions how it is possible that pleasures or knowledge are both diverse yet still form a unity that justifies the common concept. It is not about the individual concrete phenomena, whose obvious diversity is trivial, but about the general that underlies them, i.e., concepts like "human," "the beautiful," or "the good" and their subdivisions.[31]

In the Platonic Theory of Forms, to which Socrates here alludes, such concepts are regarded as "Platonic forms," that is, as independently existing, unchangeable metaphysical entities. The forms are causative powers, they evoke in the visible world the phenomena corresponding to them. However, a fundamental problem of this Platonic model emerges: on the one hand, the individual forms are regarded as separate, unified, immutable entities, thus strictly distinct from each other as well as from the sensually perceivable appearances; on the other hand, they are still closely connected to the realm of sensory objects and are somehow present there, for they cause the existence and nature of everything that arises and perishes there. The Platonic form is a stable, delimited unity and appears simultaneously as a limitless multiplicity, uniting opposites. This appears paradoxical and is now to be comprehended.[32]

Exploration of graded reality[edit]

Classification of letters (Philebus 18b–d; Scheme by Dorothea Frede)

Socrates illustrates the concept using examples. "Speech sound" and "tone" are general terms that encompass an unlimited variety of individual acoustic phenomena. Language consists of sounds, music[33] of tones. Anyone who only knows the general concepts of "sound" and "tone" and the existence of a multitude of corresponding individual phenomena still possesses no useful knowledge. One is only linguistically or musically competent if one knows the number and types of relevant sounds or tones, i.e., can fully and correctly classify the individual elements of the respective set. To this end, one starts from the most general overarching concept, the category of "Linguistic utterance" or "tone". One determines what subcategories this category consists of and how these in turn are divided into types and subtypes. Thus, one progresses from the general to the specific and captures the structure of the relevant field of knowledge. In the field of linguistic sounds, for example, it turns out that they divide into consonants and vowels. Among consonants, voiceless and voiced are to be distinguished, and the voiceless ones in turn have two subtypes. At the lowest level, one then reaches the individual sounds that are not further divisible. One finds out how many of them there are and to which classes they each belong. Similarly, one must proceed with the overarching concepts of "pleasure" and "insight" (or "reason") if one wants to become knowledgeable.[34] This system of methodically carried out concept classification is today known under the designation Dihairesis (Division).[35]

Classification of pleasure and reason into a classification system[edit]

However, Socrates first brings up another consideration, with which he returns to the initial question of the ranking of goods. He suggests examining the possibility that neither pleasure nor reason is the highest good, but rather a third thing that is superior to both. The highest good can only be "the Good", the absolute Good, which is surpassed by nothing and lacks nothing for perfection. This can apply neither to pleasure nor to reason. A pleasant life without mental function would be similar to that of a lower animal, which is neither aware of the past nor the future and does not even appreciate its present well-being, and a rational life without the capacity for sensation does not seem desirable. Both factors are thus required, and neither can be equated with the absolute Good. It remains to be clarified which of them is more valuable. Protarchus fears that pleasure will fare poorly, but does not want to abandon the effort for truth.[36]

Before the new investigation can begin, the general question of the classification of the entirety of being must be clarified. The entire reality can be divided into four categories: the Unlimited (ápeiron) or boundlessness, the Limit (péras) or the limit-like, the mixture of these two, and the cause of the mixture. Everything capable of being increased or decreased, such as "warm" and "cold", "big" and "small", "fast" and "slow", falls into the category of the Unlimited, while equality and all mathematically expressible data belong to the limit-like as definite sizes. The mixture of these two categories comes about because certain limits are set to the naturally unlimited, thus creating structures dependent on numbers. For instance, music arises from a certain mixture of high and low, fast and slow, which is based on numerical ratios. Health, too, is a certain mixture of factors that alone would cause excess and illness. Such mixtures are not arbitrary and random, but are orderly and moderate. Their cause – the fourth category – is what curbs the potentially unlimited with measure and order, ensures the right mixture ratios, and thus produces all that is beautiful and valuable.[37]

Pleasure and displeasure are now classified into this categorization. By "pleasure," all pleasant feelings are meant, and by "displeasure," all unpleasant ones.[38] Both belong to the potentially increasable and thus Unlimited. The mixed human life is to be assigned to the third category, to the things created by limiting the Unlimited. Reason has the task of ensuring the right mixture ratio. Thus, it belongs to the fourth category, to the causes of the mixture, which provide structure to the unordered and measureless. This applies not only to reason in humans but also analogously to the reason that governs the entire cosmos and orders it. The cosmic reason ensures, for example, the regular movements of celestial bodies and the change of seasons. Only animated beings can be rational; as reason in humans presupposes a soul, so must the rationally and beautifully ordered cosmos have a soul, the World Soul.[39]

Closer examination of pleasure and pain[edit]

Two main types of pleasure and pain[edit]

With the next step of the investigation, Socrates returns to the question of the types of pleasure and pain. He begins by considering the origin of both states of the human psyche. He sees their cause in the category, not the category to which pleasure and pain belong, but that of the psyche, for the psyche is the locus of both states, insofar as they occur concretely in humans. The psyche belongs to the category of things characterized by mixing, created by the limitation of the unlimited. In living beings, nature has created a harmonious order through rational mixing and limiting of potentially unlimited factors. This is evident, among other things, in health. Such a harmonious state is neither characterized by pleasure nor by pain. Both arise only when the harmony is disturbed and dissolves. Each such disturbance is felt as pain; its remediation is accompanied by a return to natural harmony, which is experienced as pleasure. For example, hunger and thirst are forms of pain resulting from deficiencies – disturbances of a natural balance; their elimination by addressing the deficiency is associated with pleasure. Similarly, an unnatural excess of heat or cold causes pain, while returning to harmony through cooling or warming creates a pleasant feeling.[40]

The phenomena mentioned represent a first type of pleasure and pain, which is triggered by current physical conditions. A second type arises in the soul through the mere anticipation of pleasurable and painful experiences; its cause is the memory of corresponding experiences. It is also important to note that there is a third state besides the pleasurable and painful one. This is the harmonious and undisturbed state, where pleasure and pain do not occur excessively. Avoiding strong fluctuations between pleasure and pain is characteristic of a life shaped by reason.[41]

Next, Socrates turns to the type of pleasure and pain that is not a reaction to current physical processes. It is triggered by imaginations that arise from memory. Here, he discusses a pleasure that is produced by the soul alone, without the body. The soul searches in the world of its memories and imaginations for pleasure. Such striving manifests as desire for something. Desire is always a striving for the opposite of the current state; emptiness calls for the need for fullness. One must already know the opposite in order to desire it. Only the soul is capable of this, for only it has memories. The body is limited to the present and can therefore desire nothing. Thus, all desires are purely of the soul.[42]

Truth and illusion in pleasure and pain[edit]

Next, the mixture of pleasure and pain is examined more closely. The question arises as to what these sensations have to do with reality and illusion.

Through the interplay of sensations triggered by the body with purely mental feelings, different mixtures of pleasure and pain arise. When someone suffers from a physical deficiency – an "emptiness" – his pain is either alleviated or intensified by his concurrent imaginations, depending on whether he expects the regaining of the desired fullness or associates the memory of fullness with hopelessness. Imaginations and expectations that generate feelings can be realistic or erroneous. Thus, they each have a specific relation to truth and falsehood. Likewise, according to Socrates' thesis, the sensations of pleasure and pain they evoke are related to truth and falsehood. This means that there are "true" and "false" pleasures. A pleasure experienced in a dream or in madness is of a different quality than one that has a relation to reality. One must distinguish between justified and illusory pleasure and pain; a pleasure based on an illusionary basis is false, lacking a relation to truth. Protarchus sees it differently. For him, pleasure always has the same nature, whether its cause is real or merely imagined. An opinion can be false, but pleasure is always "true" by its mere existence.[43]

However, Protarchus admits that both opinions and pleasures can have the quality of badness. This leads to the counter-argument of Socrates, who claims similar things for falsehood: Like an opinion, a joy or pain can be misplaced. The qualities "false" and "true" depend on the truth content. Socrates wants to transfer this determination to the associated sensations: It is possible to feel pleasure or pain about something only because one is mistaken about it. Then one not only has a false opinion about it, but the pleasure or pain is also based on a false premise, is misplaced, and thus "false". Protarchus rejects this. He insists that only the opinion is false. To call pleasure "false" as well he finds absurd.[44]

Opinions arise, as Socrates now explains, from the comparison of perceptions with memories of earlier perceptions. This comparison can go wrong; perceptions and the memories of them can be erroneous. Socrates compares the soul, in which the memories are recorded, to a book that contains true and false reports recorded by a writer and illustrated by a painter. The recordings in the memory along with the images trigger hopes and fears, pleasant and unpleasant feelings in the soul that views them. Since some of the recordings are false and much of what is hoped for or feared will not occur, the pleasure and pain generated by such memories and expectations are also illusory. Like an inaccurate opinion, it has no correlate in reality and is thus false. Bad people have false recordings, they live in illusions, and their pleasures are "false," for they are merely ridiculous imitations of true pleasures. The badness of bad pleasures is based on their falsehood. Protarchus agrees with part of these considerations but disagrees with the last thesis: He does not see that badness must necessarily be due to falsehood. From his perspective, pleasure and pain can indeed be bad, insofar as they are associated with bad things, but this badness is not like that of opinions a consequence of their falsehood, it does not consist in a certain relation to truth and falsehood.[45]

Following this, Socrates introduces a new argument. He points out that the judgment about the intensity of pleasures and pains depends on the perspective from which one views them when assessing them comparatively. This dependence on perspective he compares to optical illusions, to show that there can be falsehoods in pleasures just as there can be in sensory perceptions.[46]

Pleasurable, painful, and moderate living[edit]

Socrates now chooses a new approach. The starting point is the observation that only relatively strong bodily changes are perceived and provoke pleasure and pain. Therefore, there is not only a life shaped by pleasure and a life shaped by suffering, but also a third, neutral way of living where pleasure and pain hardly appear because the fluctuations in body condition are weak. With this statement, Socrates counters the doctrine of certain influential philosophers,[47] who only distinguish between pleasure and pain and claim that pleasure consists of nothing other than the absence of pain or freedom from pain, thus in the neutral state. By defining pleasure merely as the absence of pain, they deny it any independent reality. Thus, they prove to be the sharpest opponents of Hedonism.[48]

An argument by the pleasure-hostile philosophers could be: The strongest forms of pleasure and pain generate the greatest desires. Sick people experience more severe deficiencies than healthy ones. Therefore, they have more intense desires and feel stronger pleasure when these are satisfied. Their pleasure exceeds that of the healthy not in quantity but in intensity. Similarly, it is with the extravagant, who tend to excess: Their pleasure is more intense than that of the prudent and moderate, who do not overdo anything. This means: A poor state of body and soul enables the greatest pleasure. Thus, pleasure has its origin not in excellence (aretḗ), but in its opposite.[49]

For the purpose of testing the argument, Socrates first considers the three types of pleasure: those caused solely by physical conditions, those purely mental, and those caused by both factors. It turns out that in all three types, the most intense pleasures are by no means particularly pure – that is, free from aspects of displeasure. Rather, all of them are characterized by a significant admixture of displeasure. In the case of purely mental pleasures, this can be well observed in the theater, for example, in a tragedy, where the audience sheds tears and rejoices at the same time. In comedy, too, the mixture becomes apparent: The audience laughs, thus feeling pleasure, but the enjoyment is based on envy, a negative emotion, which is a form of displeasure. It is joy about an evil. One rejoices because the theater characters are ridiculous and fall victim to their ignorance and inability. Thus, pleasure and displeasure are mixed. This happens not only when watching events in the theater but also in the tragedy and comedy of life. The same applies to feelings such as anger, longing, grief, fear, and jealousy. All of these are not pure but mixed with pleasure and displeasure.[50]

Socrates has shown that many of the pleasures desired by humans – especially the most intense ones – cannot be explained as states of pure pleasure, but are based on a specific mixture of pleasure and displeasure. From this perspective, the designation "false pleasure" is justified. True or genuine are therefore only pure pleasures, i.e., pleasures that neither arise from the elimination of a displeasure nor themselves have an admixture of displeasure. The pure pleasures consist, as Socrates now explains, not in the absence of displeasure, but have their own reality and nature. They relate, for example, to beautiful colors and shapes as well as to pleasant smells and sounds. This also includes the joy of learning, of gaining knowledge. Such joys are moderate in contrast to the violent pleasures. Socrates emphasizes that it only depends on the purity of the pleasure, not on its quantity or intensity; the slightest pure pleasure is more pleasant, more beautiful, and truer than the greatest impure pleasure.[51]

Transience of pleasure[edit]

Socrates now raises another topic: the relationship of pleasure to Being and Becoming. This refers to the philosophical distinction between the eternal, perfect, and self-sufficient Being on the one hand, and the transient, imperfect, and dependent Becoming on the other. Being is cause, Becoming is caused. All pleasure arises and passes away. Since it belongs to the realm of the caused and transient, it has no true being, but only becoming. From this, its inferiority is evident, for all that becomes and is subject to decay is by nature defective and always in need of something else. Here Socrates returns to the initial question of the dialogue. His argument is: Everything that becomes is oriented towards a superior Being. Becoming is not an end in itself, but every process of becoming takes place for the sake of a Being. Thus, the Good as the highest value cannot be something that arises for the sake of something else, but only that for which Becoming arises. In this, Socrates believes he has shown that equating pleasure with the Good is ridiculous. He adds further arguments. Protarchus recognizes the cogency of the proof.[52]

Investigation of reason[edit]

Following the examination of the value of pleasure, Socrates subjects reason and knowledge to a similar scrutiny. Again, the question of "purity" and "truth" arises, here relating to the accuracy and reliability of the results provided by various fields of knowledge – crafts and sciences. When considering the utility of these fields from this perspective, the superiority of those disciplines involving calculation and measurement over the less precise ones, which rely on observation and estimation, becomes evident. At the same time, it becomes clear that pure theory, which deals with absolute facts, is fundamentally superior to Empirical science, which only deals with approximations. In this sense, pure geometry is above architecture as applied geometry.[53]

Of crucial importance for the systematics of science is the quality of the approach. In this respect, Dialectics, the expert, systematic analysis following the rules of logic, is superior to all other sciences. It deserves precedence because it provides the clearest and most accurate results with the highest degree of truth. Its object is the realm of the unchangeable being, to which absolute purity and truth belong. The more transient something is, the farther it is from the truth. There can be no reliable knowledge about changeable things.[54]

Hierarchy of goods[edit]

From the considerations so far, the hierarchy of goods emerges. Reason is closer to the True, the Real, the absolutely Good than pleasure, hence it stands above it in the hierarchy. However, reason is not identical with the Good, for otherwise it would suffice for man alone and pleasure would be unnecessary.[55]

In determining what is good in terms of human life, Socrates draws on the already gained knowledge that life is mixed with pleasure and displeasure, and therefore it depends on the right mix. Human life is a mixture of different factors. Now the question arises as to which types of knowledge should be included in the mix. It turns out that not only the highest and most reliable knowledge, pure theory, is needed for a successful life, but also some empirical and technical knowledge despite its inaccuracy. No subordinate knowledge can ever be harmful if the superior one is present, thus all types of knowledge are welcome. The case is different with pleasure. The greatest and most intense pleasures are very harmful, as they destroy knowledge. Therefore, only the "true" pleasures, which are pure and in harmony with temperance, are permissible.[56]

Now it is to be investigated what constitutes the good, valuable mix that enables a successful life. The question arises whether this crucial factor is more related to pleasure or to reason. Socrates finds the answer simple, even trivial, because everyone knows it: The quality of a mix always depends on the right measure and proportionality. Where these are lacking, there is always ruinous chaos. The right measure manifests itself in the form of beauty and excellence. Moreover, truth must always be mixed in. In human life, the Good does not appear immediately in its unity, but it can be grasped as beauty, appropriateness, and truth. The efficacy of the Good has "found refuge in the nature of the Beautiful".[57]

From these considerations, the exact determination of the hierarchical order of goods finally emerges. Reason is far superior to pleasure, as it has a greater share in truth as well as in measure and beauty. The highest of the goods below the absolutely Good is the right measure, followed by beauty, and thirdly reason.[58] Fourth place is occupied by the sciences, arts, and true opinions, and fifth by the pure pleasures. This finding remains unchanged even if all oxen, horses, and other animals collectively advocate for the precedence of pleasure by pursuing it. Protarchus agrees to this also in the name of Philebus. Philebus no longer speaks.[59]

Philosophy[edit]

The starting point of the discussion is the old question, already addressed by Hesiod, whether pleasure or reason, knowledge and virtue should take precedence. Plato does not limit himself to clarifying this question but uses the topic to outline a philosophical theory of the entire reality of being and becoming.[60]

A main idea developed in the Philebus is the extraordinary importance of measure. For Plato's Socrates, measure plays a central role both in the order of the world and in human life as the basis of all that is good and beautiful. This is contrasted with the immoderation of hedonistic excess. This emphasis on the mathematical order of the world and its philosophical exploration, as well as the opposition between limitation and boundlessness, reveals the influence of Pythagorean thought.[61]

Difficulties arise in the connection of the four classes of beings introduced by Plato's Socrates with the Platonic theory of forms. It is disputed whether the classes – or at least some of them – are to be understood as forms. In particular, the assumption that even the Unlimited is a form is problematic and controversial. Moreover, it has been discussed whether the forms fit into one of the four categories or are identifiable with one of them.[62]

Moreover, it is unclear what role the theory of forms plays in the Philebus. Since it is not explicitly addressed, it has been suggested that it is not present here. This assumption fits the hypothesis that Plato distanced himself from the theory of forms in his last creative period, having abandoned it or at least considered it in need of revision. However, Plato's Socrates in the Philebus places great emphasis on the distinction between the superior realm of unchanging being and the world of becoming and passing away dependent on it. Thus, Plato at least held onto a core component of the concept underlying the theory of forms. The question of whether he has changed his fundamental position is highly disputed in research. The view of the "Unitarians," who believe he consistently maintained a coherent perspective, is opposed to the "development hypothesis" of the "Revisionists," who assume a deviation from the theory of forms or at least from its "classical" variant. From a Unitarian perspective, the worldview presented in the Philebus is interpreted as a response to the problematization of the theory of forms in the dialogue Parmenides.[63]

Expressions like "becoming to being" (génesis eis ousían)[64] indicate Plato's engagement with the question of how to explain the connection between the two fundamentally different realms of being and becoming. This problem, known in modern research as Chorismos, occupied him intensely.[65]

Particularly intensive is the discussion over the difficult interpretation and coherence of Socrates' argumentation for the "falsity" of pleasures. It examines what exactly the term "false" means in this context and to which aspect of certain pleasures it refers. It is debated whether for Plato's Socrates a false pleasure, due to its illusory character, is not a real pleasure but only appears to be among pleasures, or whether it is a falsehood analogous to the error of an opinion. In the latter case, the falsehood is a defect that does not prevent an actual pleasure from existing.[66]

Another controversial topic is the relationship of the metaphysics of the Philebus to Plato's unwritten doctrines” or “doctrine of principles,” which he never fixed in writing for fundamental considerations. A highly disputed scholarly opinion suggests that this doctrine can be reconstructed in outline from individual hints in the dialogues and statements in other sources (the “Tübingen and Milan Plato School”, “Tübingen Paradigm”). Proponents of this hypothesis believe they have also found indications of the doctrine of principles in the Philebus, or interpret statements in the dialogue in light of the doctrine of principles.[67] According to an interpretation based on this understanding, the expressions used in the Philebus, “limitation” and “the Unlimited,” correspond to the terms “the One” (to hen, unity) and “unlimited” or “indeterminate duality” (ahóristos dyás) of the doctrine of principles. The “More and Less” in the Philebus, the capability for increase and decrease, is accordingly “the Great and Small” or “the Great-Small” (to méga kai to mikrón) of the doctrine of principles; with this concept, Plato is said to have described the indeterminate duality.[68]

Furthermore, it is debated whether Plato provides a comprehensive interpretation of pleasure that encompasses all types of pleasure, or whether the types are so fundamentally different for him that he refrains from a universally valid determination of the nature of pleasure. The former interpretation is the traditional and predominant one.[69]

Mark Moes highlights a therapeutic goal of the dialogue. According to his interpretation, the primary concern is that Socrates acts as a therapist, a "soul doctor," who, like a physician, first makes a diagnosis and then turns to therapy. Accordingly, it is about the health of the soul, which Socrates sees as harmed by hedonism. His efforts aim to lead Protarchus to the right way of life. This effect is also intended for readers inclined towards hedonism.[70]

Plato (Roman copy of the Greek portrait of Plato by Silanion, Glyptothek Munich)

Reception[edit]

Antiquity and the Middle Ages[edit]

Although Plato's student Aristotle never names Philebus explicitly, he engaged deeply with the Platonic theory of pleasure, and often refers to it in content.[71] He might also have had the Philebus in mind when discussing the unwritten teachings. Aristotle’s student Theophrastus of Eresus opposed the thesis of Plato's Socrates that there is a false pleasure, and adhered to the view of Protarchus that all pleasure is “true”.[72]

The rhetorician and literary critic Dionysius of Halicarnassus praised Philebus; he noted approvingly that Plato had preserved the Socratic style in this work.[73] In the tetralogical order of Plato's works, which was apparently introduced in the 1st century BC in a now-lost work of the scholar Thrasyllus,[74] Philebus belongs to the third tetralogy.[citation needed] The historian of philosophy Diogenes Laertius classified it among the “ethical” writings and gave the alternative title “On Pleasure”. Plutarch attempted to link the four classes of being, which Plato's Socrates discusses in Philebus, with the five “greatest kinds”[75] named in the dialogue Sophist by adding a fifth class and interpreting the classes as reflections of the kinds.[76] The famous physician Galen wrote a now-lost treatise “On the Transitions in the Philebus”, in which he examined the reasoning processes in the dialogue.[77] In the 3rd century, a Middle Platonist living in Athens named Eubulus wrote a now-lost treatise that included a discussion on Philebus.[78] Another Middle Platonist, Democritus, who also lived in the 3rd century, engaged with the dialogue; whether he wrote a commentary is unclear.[79]

In Late Antiquity, the Neoplatonists showed a great interest in Philebus. They focused particularly on the metaphysical aspects of the dialogue, though the ethical aspects were also considered.[80] Plotinus († 270), the founder of Neoplatonism, frequently referred to Philebus in his treatise titled How the Multiplicity of Ideas Came About, and Concerning the Good.[81] Plotinus' most famous student Porphyry († 301/305) wrote a Philebus commentary, of which only fragments survive. His fellow student Amelius may also have written a commentary. Porphyry’s student Iamblichus († around 320/325), a leading representative of late antique Neoplatonism, instructed his school to study Philebus as one of the twelve dialogues he considered most important.[82] He wrote a commentary on it, of which only a few fragments are preserved.[83] Also, the Neoplatonists Proclus and Marinus of Neapolis, teaching in Athens in the 5th century, commented on the dialogue. Marinus, a student of Proclus, burned his extensive commentary after the philosopher Isidore, whom he had asked for an opinion, criticized the work and expressed the opinion that Proclus' commentary was sufficient.[84] It is possible that Theodorus of Asine and Syrianus also wrote commentaries. No single work from this literature has survived. Only the transcript of a lecture by Damascius († after 538) on the Philebus is preserved. It was previously mistakenly attributed to Olympiodorus the Younger. Damascius critically addressed Proclus' interpretation of Philebus.[85]

In the Middle Ages, the dialogue was known to some Byzantine scholars,[who?] but the Latin-speaking educated of the West had no access to the work.

Early Modern period[edit]

The beginning of Philebus in the first edition, Venice 1513

Philebus was rediscovered in the West during the era of Renaissance humanism. The humanist and Plato scholar Marsilio Ficino published a Latin translation in 1484 in Florence as part of the complete edition of his Plato translations, while the first edition of the Greek text, edited by Markos Musuros, was published in September 1513 in Venice by Aldo Manuzio, as part of the first Greek edition of Plato's works. Ficino held the Philebus in especially high esteem; when his patron, the statesman Cosimo de’ Medici, lay on his deathbed in July 1464, Ficino had read an early version of the Latin text to him. Already in early 1464, Cosimo had expressed his special interest in Philebus, “Plato’s book on the highest good,” as he sought nothing more eagerly than the knowledge of the surest way to happiness. Additionally, Ficino wrote a commentary on the dialogue, the third and final version of which was printed in 1496, and he delivered lectures to a large audience on the issues discussed in Philebus. His goal was to promote Platonism and push back against the influence of contemporary Aristotelians.[86]

Modern period[edit]

Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling valued Philebus. In his 1794 essay Timaeus, a youthful work, he dealt with the question of the emergence of a perceivable world. In doing so, he drew on Philebus. He was particularly interested in the four kinds, which he called “general world concepts,” and the “becoming to being.” He emphasized that the four kinds should not be understood as concepts of entities, they are not designations for something existent, but categories for all real existent. The Unlimited should be interpreted as the principle of reality of all that is real, also as the principle of quality, while limitation as the principle of quantity and form of all that is real. In his dialogue Bruno (1802), Schelling referred to Philebus when determining the subject of philosophy.[87]

Hegel found in Philebus “the Esoteric of Platonic Philosophy”; this meant the speculative, which, although published, remains hidden “to those who do not have the interest to grasp it.” Pleasure apparently belonged to the realm of the concrete, but one must understand that pure thoughts are the substantial, deciding over all else that is concrete. The nature of pleasure arises from the nature of the infinite, the indeterminate, to which it belongs.[88]

Friedrich Schleiermacher, who valued the content of Philebus, commented disparagingly on its literary quality. He found that the dialogue did not offer pure enjoyment that he believed one would expect from other works of Plato; the dialogical character did not quite emerge, the dialogic was only an outer form.[89] The philologist Ulrich von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff also expressed his disapproval of the literary design; he considered the Philebus to be a school disputation without artistic appeal, that was merely the shadow of a Socratic dialogue, with a rigid conversational form and all of its dramatic power extinguished. Regarding the content of the dialogue, however, he believed Plato had significant things to say.[90] Nietzsche also criticized the work, chacterizing the “question and answer game” within the Philebus as a “transparent shell for the communication of ready-made constructions”.[91] A different view was held by Paul Friedländer; he believed the artistic quality was often misunderstood by modern readers, attributing their lack of understanding for the “dialogical liveliness” as evident in the misjudged punctuation in the text editions.[92]

In 1903, the Neo-Kantian Paul Natorp presented his treatise Plato’s Theory of Ideas, in which he also extensively addressed Philebus, describing it as a profound psychological investigation. He also regarded it as one of the most important dialogues for Platonic logic.[93] However, Natorp criticized Plato for adhering to a stark contrast between the changeable and the unchangeable, and not making the final step toward a science of becoming, a “logical foundation of empirical science.”[94]

Hans-Georg Gadamer examined Philebus from a phenomenological perspective.[95] He also later intensely engaged with the dialogue, which he interpreted hermeneutically. He attempted to show with Philebus that the idea of the good, according to Plato’s view, is immanent in human life and an aspect of lived experience. In doing so, he brought Plato’s way of thinking closer to that of Aristotle; he believed that Aristotelian thought was anticipated in Philebus. With this approach of the habilitation thesis, he was under the influence of his teacher Martin Heidegger, from whose viewpoint he later partially distanced himself.[96] In a Heidegger-oriented understanding, Gadamer found Plato’s thoughts on “true” or “false” pleasure comprehensible. The pleasure thus conceived is “true, insofar as it is supposed in it that being is pleasurable, which is pleasurable.” The disposition of pleasure is always “understood from its having discovered the being, ‘in which’ it is had.” Plato sees it “as a way of encountering the world.”[97] This concept of pleasure corresponded to Gadamer’s own view; he assumed with Heidegger that affects are a distinct way of discovering being, independent of their connection with opinions.[98] Moreover, Gadamer equated the good with the beautiful, thus “aestheticizing” Platonic ethics. The engagement with Philebus, particularly with the dialectic understanding presented therein, played a significant role in the development of Gadamer’s philosophy.[99]

The philosopher Herbert Marcuse engaged in his 1938 published paper On the Critique of Hedonism with Philebus. He found that Plato was the first thinker to develop the concept of true and false need, of true and false pleasure, thereby introducing truth and falsehood as categories applicable to each individual pleasure. This subordinated happiness to the criterion of truth. Pleasure must be accessible to the distinction between truth and falsehood, right and wrong, otherwise happiness is inseparably linked to misfortune. The basis of the distinction, however, could not lie in the individual sensation of pleasure as such. Rather, a pleasure becomes untrue when the object it refers to is “in itself” not pleasurable. The question of truth concerns not only the object but also the subject of pleasure. Plato connects the goodness of man with the truth of pleasure, thus making pleasure a moral issue. This places pleasure under the claim of society and brings it into the realm of duty. By assigning to “pure” pleasure, which he alone approves of, exclusively inanimate objects as objects, thus the things farthest removed from the societal life process, he separates it “from all essential personal relations”.[100]

Donald Davidson took a “revisionist” stance on the Philebus: Plato, when he wrote this dialogue, no longer believed that the theory of forms could be the main foundation of an ethical concept. He had abandoned the idea of a close link between forms and values. Therefore, he had to find a new approach for his ethics.[101]

Jacques Derrida engaged in his essay La double séance (“The Double Session”), part of his 1972 published work La dissémination, with writing and Mimesis. He chose as his starting point the passage in Philebus where the soul is compared to a book containing the recordings of a scribe and the images of a painter.[102]

Texts and translations[edit]

  • Greek text and parallel English translation at Perseus
  • Bury, Robert G. (ed.). The Philebus of Plato. Cambridge University Press, 1897. Greek text, Introduction and notes.
  • Plato: Statesman, Philebus, Ion. Greek with translation by Harold N. Fowler and W. R. M. Lamb. Loeb Classical Library 164. Harvard Univ. Press (originally published 1925). ISBN 978-0674991828 HUP listing
  • Dorothea Frede: Philebus, Plato, translated, with introduction and notes. Hackett Publishing, Indianapolis 1993. ISBN 978-0872201705
  • Seth Benardete: The Tragedy and Comedy of Life. Plato’s Philebus. University of Chicago Press, Chicago/London 1993. ISBN 0-226-04239-1
  • Fowler translation at Perseus
  • Jowett translation at StandardEbooks
  • Plato. Opera, volume II. Oxford Classical Texts. ISBN 978-0198145417
  • Plato. Complete Works. Ed. J. M. Cooper and D. S. Hutchinson. Hackett, 1997. ISBN 978-0872203495

References[edit]

  1. ^ Friedländer (1969) page 306.
  2. ^ Jowett, Chapter 1.
  3. ^ Schofield.
  4. ^ Schofield, 'Plato', Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward Craig. Routledge. page 419.
  5. ^ Michael Erler: Plato, Basel 2007, p. 253 f.; Michel Narcy: Plato. Philebus. In: Richard Goulet (ed.): Dictionnaire des philosophes antiques, Vol. 5, Part 1, Paris 2012, p. 713–719, here: 713 f. For an early dating, see Robin A. H. Waterfield: The Place of the Philebus in Plato’s Dialogues. In: Phronesis 25, 1980, p. 270–305. Cf. Gerard R. Ledger: Re-counting Plato, Oxford 1989, p. 198 f.; Holger Thesleff: Platonic Patterns, Las Vegas 2009, p. 344–346.
  6. ^ Dorothea Frede: Plato: Philebus. Translation and Commentary, Göttingen 1997, p. 385; Michael Erler: Plato, Basel 2007, p. 254.
  7. ^ See, for example, Robin A. H. Waterfield: On the text of some passages of Plato’s Philebus. In: Liverpool Classical Monthly 5, 1980, p. 57–64.
  8. ^ Oxford, Bodleian Library, Clarke 39 (= „Codex B“ of the Plato textual transmission).
  9. ^ Corpus dei Papiri Filosofici Greci e Latini (CPF), Part 1, Vol. 1***, Firenze 1999, p. 285–289, 508–512.
  10. ^ Plato, Philebus 16a–b.
  11. ^ See about the character of Socrates and its role Thomas Alexander Szlezák: Plato and the Writtenness of Philosophy, Part 2: The Image of the Dialectician in Plato's Late Dialogues, Berlin 2004, pp. 210–217; Reginald Hackforth: Plato’s Examination of Pleasure, Cambridge 1958 (reprint of the 1945 edition), pp. 7 f.; Dorothea Frede: Plato: Philebus. Translation and Commentary, Göttingen 1997, pp. 387–389
    Georgia Mouroutsou
    The Metaphor of Mixture in the Platonic Dialogues Sophist and Philebus, Sankt Augustin 2010, pp. 199 f.
  12. ^ Alfred Edward Taylor: Plato: Philebus and Epinomis, Folkestone 1972 (reprint of the 1956 edition), pp. 11 f.
  13. ^ Dorothea Frede: Plato: Philebus. Translation and Commentary, Göttingen 1997, p. 95; Richard Goulet: Philèbe. In: Richard Goulet (ed.): Dictionary of Ancient Philosophers, Vol. 5, Part 1, Paris 2012, p. 302.
  14. ^ See about the role of Philebus Thomas Alexander Szlezák: Plato and the Writtenness of Philosophy, Part 2: The Image of the Dialectician in Plato's Late Dialogues, Berlin 2004, pp. 203 f.
  15. ^ Michael Erler: Plato, Basel 2007, pp. 254–256. Cf. Reginald Hackforth: Plato’s Examination of Pleasure, Cambridge 1958 (reprint of the 1945 edition), pp. 4–7; Justin C. B. Gosling, Christopher C. W. Taylor: The Greeks on Pleasure, Oxford 1982, pp. 157–164; Maurizio Migliori: Man between Pleasure, Intelligence, and the Good, Milan 1993, pp. 352–357; Dorothea Frede: Plato: Philebus. Translation and Commentary, Göttingen 1997, pp. 390–394.
  16. ^ Plato, Philebus 11c, 26b.
  17. ^ Plato, Philebus 12b, 22c. Cf. Hans-Georg Gadamer: The Idea of the Good between Plato and Aristotle. In: Gadamer: Collected Works, Vol. 7, Tübingen 1991, pp. 128–227, here: 187.
  18. ^ Paul Friedländer: Plato, Vol. 3, 3rd, revised edition, Berlin 1975, pp. 288 f.; Reginald Hackforth: Plato’s Examination of Pleasure, Cambridge 1958 (reprint of the 1945 edition), pp. 6; Hans-Georg Gadamer: The Idea of the Good between Plato and Aristotle. In: Gadamer: Collected Works, Vol. 7, Tübingen 1991, pp. 128–227, here: 186 f.; Sylvain Delcomminette: The Philebus of Plato, Leiden 2006, pp. 34 f.
  19. ^ Luc Brisson: Protarchus. In: Richard Goulet (ed.): Dictionary of Ancient Philosophers, Vol. 5, Part 2, Paris 2012, p. 1708; Michel Narcy: Plato. Philebus. In: Richard Goulet (ed.): Dictionary of Ancient Philosophers, Vol. 5, Part 1, Paris 2012, pp. 713–719, here: 714; Debra Nails: The People of Plato, Indianapolis 2002, p. 257; Dorothea Frede: Plato: Philebus. Translation and Commentary, Göttingen 1997, p. 95; Michael Erler: Plato, Basel 2007, p. 255.
  20. ^ Plato, Philebus 19b.
  21. ^ For this identification, see Dorothea Frede: Plato: Philebus. Translation and Commentary, Göttingen 1997, p. 95; against it are Debra Nails: The People of Plato, Indianapolis 2002, p. 257 and Luc Brisson: Protarchus. In: Richard Goulet (ed.): Dictionary of Ancient Philosophers, Vol. 5, Part 2, Paris 2012, p. 1708.
  22. ^ Plato, Apology 20a–c; cf. Dorothea Frede: Plato: Philebus. Translation and Commentary, Göttingen 1997, p. 95.
  23. ^ Plato, Philebus 58a–b.
  24. ^ Aristotle, Physics 197b. Cf. William David Ross (ed.): Aristotle’s Physics, Oxford 1936, p. 522.
  25. ^ See also Thomas Alexander Szlezák: Plato and the Writtenness of Philosophy, Part 2: The Image of the Dialectician in Plato's Late Dialogues, Berlin 2004, pp. 204–209.
  26. ^ Friedrich Schleiermacher: Philebus. Introduction. In: Friedrich Daniel Ernst Schleiermacher: On the Philosophy of Plato, edited by Peter M. Steiner, Hamburg 1996, pp. 303–312, here: 303.
  27. ^ Michael Erler: Plato, Basel 2007, p. 256; Sylvain Delcomminette: Plato’s Philebus, Leiden 2006, pp. 16 f.; Dorothea Frede: Plato: Philebus. Translation and Commentary, Göttingen 1997, pp. 379 f.
  28. ^ See on the appreciation of the comic theory Salvatore Cerasuolo: The Treatment of the Comic in the Philebus. In: Paolo Cosenza (ed.): Plato’s Philebus and Its Fate, Naples 1996, pp. 173–190.
  29. ^ Plato, Philebus 11a–12b. See also Seth Benardete: The Tragedy and Comedy of Life, Chicago 1993, pp. 92–104.
  30. ^ Plato, Philebus 12c–14b. See also Seth Benardete: The Tragedy and Comedy of Life, Chicago 1993, pp. 105–110; Gebhard Löhr: The Problem of the One and Many in Plato’s “Philebus”, Göttingen 1990, pp. 12–21.
  31. ^ Plato, Philebus 14c–15a. See also Gebhard Löhr: The Problem of the One and Many in Plato’s “Philebus”, Göttingen 1990, pp. 22–69.
  32. ^ Plato, Philebus 15a–16c. See also Constance C. Meinwald: One/Many Problems: Philebus 14c1–15c3. In: Phronesis 41, 1996, pp. 95–103; Fernando Muniz, George Rudebusch: Plato, Philebus 15b: a problem solved. In: Classical Quarterly 54, 2004, pp. 394–405; Cynthia Hampton: Pleasure, Knowledge, and Being, Albany 1990, pp. 21–23; Georgia Mouroutsou: The Metaphor of Mixing in the Platonic Dialogues Sophistes and Philebus, Sankt Augustin 2010, pp. 204–222; Gebhard Löhr: The Problem of the One and Many in Plato’s “Philebus”, Göttingen 1990, pp. 69–100.
  33. ^ For the example from music, see Andrew Barker: Plato’s Philebus: The Numbering of a Unity. In: Eugenio Benitez (ed.): Dialogues with Plato, Edmonton 1996, pp. 143–164, here: 146–161.
  34. ^ Plato, Philebus 17a–20b. Cf. Seth Benardete: The Tragedy and Comedy of Life, Chicago 1993, pp. 119–129; Cynthia Hampton: Pleasure, Knowledge, and Being, Albany 1990, pp. 28–35; Georgia Mouroutsou: The Metaphor of the Mixture in the Platonic Dialogues Sophist and Philebus, St. Augustin 2010, pp. 247–260; Gebhard Löhr: The Problem of the One and Many in Plato’s “Philebus”, Göttingen 1990, pp. 143–178, 188–193; Sylvain Delcomminette: Le Philèbe de Platon, Leiden 2006, pp. 144–159; Maurizio Migliori: Man between Pleasure, Intelligence, and the Good, Milan 1993, pp. 104–123; Dorothea Frede: Plato: Philebus. Translation and Commentary, Göttingen 1997, pp. 146–169.
  35. ^ See Michael Schramm: Dihairesis. In: Christian Schäfer (ed.): Platon-Lexikon, Darmstadt 2007, pp. 92–95; Michael Erler: Plato, Basel 2007, pp. 369 f.
  36. ^ Plato, Philebus 20b–23b. Cf. Seth Benardete: The Tragedy and Comedy of Life, Chicago 1993, pp. 130–137; Sylvain Delcomminette: Le Philèbe de Platon, Leiden 2006, pp. 164–199; Dorothea Frede: Plato: Philebus. Translation and Commentary, Göttingen 1997, pp. 169–184.
  37. ^ Plato, Philebus 23c–27c. Cf. Seth Benardete: The Tragedy and Comedy of Life, Chicago 1993, pp. 138–156; Georgia Mouroutsou: The Metaphor of the Mixture in the Platonic Dialogues Sophist and Philebus, St. Augustin 2010, pp. 273–307; Gisela Striker: Peras and Apeiron, Göttingen 1970, pp. 41–76; Sylvain Delcomminette: Le Philèbe de Platon, Leiden 2006, pp. 201–258; Dorothea Frede: Plato: Philebus. Translation and Commentary, Göttingen 1997, pp. 184–211.
  38. ^ Dorothea Frede: Plato: Philebus. Translation and Commentary, Göttingen 1997, p. 13 Note 1.
  39. ^ Plato, Philebus 27c–31b. Cf. Seth Benardete: The Tragedy and Comedy of Life, Chicago 1993, pp. 157–165; Sylvain Delcomminette: Le Philèbe de Platon, Leiden 2006, pp. 258–285; Dorothea Frede: Plato: Philebus. Translation and Commentary, Göttingen 1997, pp. 211–221.
  40. ^ Plato, Philebus 31b–32b. See Sylvain Delcomminette: Le Philèbe de Platon, Leiden 2006, pp. 297–303.
  41. ^ Plato, Philebus 32b–33c. See Sylvain Delcomminette: Le Philèbe de Platon, Leiden 2006, pp. 303–313.
  42. ^ Plato, Philebus 33c–35d. See Sylvain Delcomminette: Le Philèbe de Platon, Leiden 2006, pp. 313–344.
  43. ^ Plato, Philebus 35d–37c. See Sylvain Delcomminette: Le Philèbe de Platon, Leiden 2006, pp. 344–357.
  44. ^ Plato, Philebus 37c–38a. See Sylvain Delcomminette: Le Philèbe de Platon, Leiden 2006, pp. 355–362.
  45. ^ Plato, Philebus 38a–41a. See Sylvain Delcomminette: Le Philèbe de Platon, Leiden 2006, pp. 362–399.
  46. ^ Plato, Philebus 41a–42c. See also Norman Mooradian: What To Do About False Pleasures of Overestimation? Philebus 41a5–42c5. In: Apeiron 28, 1995, pp. 91–112; Seth Benardete: The Tragedy and Comedy of Life, Chicago 1993, pp. 186–189; Sylvain Delcomminette: Le Philèbe de Platon, Leiden 2006, pp. 399–412.
  47. ^ Regarding who is meant here, see Malcolm Schofield: Who were οἱ δυσχερεῖς in Plato, Philebus 44 a ff.? In: Museum Helveticum 28, 1971, pp. 2–20, 181; Klaus Bringmann: Plato's Philebus and Heracleides Ponticus’ Dialogue περὶ ἡδονῆς. In: Hermes 100, 1972, pp. 523–530; Dorothea Frede: Plato: Philebus. Translation and Commentary, Göttingen 1997, pp. 268–271; Marcel van Ackeren: The Knowledge of the Good, Amsterdam 2003, p. 267 note 304.
  48. ^ Plato, Philebus 42c–44c. Cf. Sylvain Delcomminette: The Philebus of Plato, Leiden 2006, pp. 412–429.
  49. ^ Plato, Philebus 44c–45e. Cf. Sylvain Delcomminette: The Philebus of Plato, Leiden 2006, pp. 429–433.
  50. ^ Plato, Philebus 45e–50d. Cf. Daniel Schulthess: Laughing at Ignorance? (Plato, Philebus 48a–50e). In: Marie-Laurence Desclos: The Laughter of the Greeks, Grenoble 2000, pp. 309–318; Seth Benardete: The Tragedy and Comedy of Life, Chicago 1993, pp. 198–208; Stefan Büttner: The Theory of Literature in Plato and its Anthropological Foundation, Tübingen 2000, pp. 96–100; Cynthia Hampton: Pleasure, Knowledge, and Being, Albany 1990, pp. 64–67; Sylvain Delcomminette: The Philebus of Plato, Leiden 2006, pp. 433–448.
  51. ^ Plato, Philebus 50e–53c. Cf. Seth Benardete: The Tragedy and Comedy of Life, Chicago 1993, pp. 209–212; Cynthia Hampton: Pleasure, Knowledge, and Being, Albany 1990, pp. 67–74; Sylvain Delcomminette: The Philebus of Plato, Leiden 2006, pp. 449–491; Dorothea Frede: Plato: Philebus. Translation and Commentary, Göttingen 1997, pp. 295–306.
  52. ^ Plato, Philebus 53c–55c. Cf. Seth Benardete: The Tragedy and Comedy of Life, Chicago 1993, pp. 213–216; Sylvain Delcomminette: The Philebus of Plato, Leiden 2006, pp. 493–506; Dorothea Frede: Plato: Philebus. Translation and Commentary, Göttingen 1997, pp. 306–318.
  53. ^ Plato, Philebus 55c–57e. Cf. John M. Cooper: Plato’s Theory of Human Good in the Philebus. In: Gail Fine (Ed.): Plato, Oxford 2000, pp. 811–826, here: 815–820; Sylvain Delcomminette: Le Philèbe de Platon, Leiden 2006, pp. 507–523.
  54. ^ Plato, Philebus 57e–59c. On the representation of dialectics in the Philebus see Thomas Alexander Szlezák: Plato and the Literacy of Philosophy, Part 2: The Image of the Dialectician in Plato's Late Dialogues, Berlin 2004, pp. 193–202; Cynthia Hampton: Pleasure, Knowledge, and Being, Albany 1990, pp. 77–79.
  55. ^ Plato, Philebus 59d–61a.
  56. ^ Plato, Philebus 61a–64a. Cf. Sylvain Delcomminette: Le Philèbe de Platon, Leiden 2006, pp. 545–556.
  57. ^ Plato, Philebus 64a–65a. Cf. Damir Barbarić: Approaching Plato, Würzburg 2009, pp. 99–112; Sylvain Delcomminette: Le Philèbe de Platon, Leiden 2006, pp. 556–577.
  58. ^ On the function of reason and its rank in the order of value see Christopher Bobonich: Plato’s Utopia Recast, Oxford 2002, pp. 162–179.
  59. ^ Plato, Philebus 65a–67b. Cf. Cynthia Hampton: Pleasure, Knowledge, and Being, Albany 1990, pp. 84–87; Sylvain Delcomminette: Le Philèbe de Platon, Leiden 2006, pp. 615–627; Dorothea Frede: Platon: Philebus. Translation and Commentary, Göttingen 1997, pp. 360–372.
  60. ^ Dorothea Frede: Plato: Philebus. Translation and Commentary, Göttingen 1997, pp. 222 f.; Michael Erler: Plato, Basel 2007, p. 259.
  61. ^ Michael Erler: Plato, Basel 2007, pp. 255 f. Cf. Dorothea Frede: Plato: Philebus. Translation and Commentary, Göttingen 1997, pp. 394–402.
  62. ^ Michael Erler: Plato, Basel 2007, p. 258; Peter J. Davis: The Fourfold Classification in Plato’s Philebus. In: Apeiron 13, 1979, pp. 124–134, here: 129–132; Gisela Striker: Peras und Apeiron, Göttingen 1970, pp. 77–81; Marcel van Ackeren: The Knowledge of the Good, Amsterdam 2003, p. 259 note 250; Cynthia Hampton: Pleasure, Knowledge, and Being, Albany 1990, pp. 49 f.; Kenneth M. Sayre: Plato’s Late Ontology, 2nd, expanded edition, Las Vegas 2005, pp. 134–136; Henry Teloh: The Development of Plato’s Metaphysics, University Park 1981, pp. 186–188; Eugenio E. Benitez: Forms in Plato’s Philebus, Assen 1989, pp. 6, 59–91; Justin Gosling: Is There a Form of the Indeterminate? In: Monique Dixsaut (Ed.): The Fracture of Pleasure, Vol. 1, Paris 1999, pp. 43–59; Maurizio Migliori: Man between Pleasure, Intelligence, and the Good, Milan 1993, pp. 450–457, 467–469.
  63. ^ Michael Erler: Plato, Basel 2007, pp. 258 f. For the implicit presence of the theory of forms in the Philebus, argue, among others, Julius M. Moravcsik: Forms, nature, and the good in the Philebus. In: Phronesis 24, 1979, pp. 81–104; Robert Fahrnkopf: Forms in the Philebus. In: Journal of the History of Philosophy 15, 1977, pp. 202–207; Eugenio E. Benitez: Forms in Plato’s Philebus, Assen 1989, pp. 3–6, 21–31, 39–42, 87–91, 129–132; Giovanni Reale: Towards a New Interpretation of Plato, 2nd, expanded edition, Paderborn 2000, pp. 358–361, 450–454; Maurizio Migliori: Man between Pleasure, Intelligence, and the Good, Milan 1993, pp. 75–84, 433 f., 450–457; Cynthia Hampton: Pleasure, Knowledge, and Being, Albany 1990, pp. 7–11, 14–21; Margherita Isnardi Parente: The Ideas in Plato's Philebus. In: Paolo Cosenza (Ed.): Plato's Philebus and Its Influence, Naples 1996, pp. 205–219. The opposing position is confessed, among others, by Roger A. Shiner: Knowledge and Reality in Plato’s Philebus, Assen 1974, pp. 11, 30, 34–37 (cautiously; cf. Roger A. Shiner: Must Philebus 59a–c Refer to Transcendent Forms? In: Journal of the History of Philosophy 17, 1979, pp. 71–77); Russell M. Dancy: The One, the Many, and the Forms: Philebus 15b1–8. In: Ancient Philosophy 4, 1984, pp. 160–193; Kenneth M. Sayre: Plato’s Late Ontology, 2nd, expanded edition, Las Vegas 2005, pp. 174–185; Henry Teloh: The Development of Plato’s Metaphysics, University Park 1981, pp. 176–188.
  64. ^ Plato, Philebus 26d.
  65. ^ Michael Erler: Plato, Basel 2007, pp. 258 f.; Michael Hoffmann: The Emergence of Order, Stuttgart 1996, pp. 113–125, 135–167, 189–207; Eugenio E. Benitez: Forms in Plato’s Philebus, Assen 1989, pp. 99–108.
  66. ^ See Dorothea Frede: Plato: Philebus. Translation and Commentary, Göttingen 1997, pp. 242–295; Seth Benardete: The Tragedy and Comedy of Life, Chicago 1993, pp. 175–186; Reinhard Brandt: True and False Affections in Plato's Philebus. In: Archive for the History of Philosophy 59, 1977, pp. 1–18; Justin C. B. Gosling, Christopher C. W. Taylor: The Greeks on Pleasure, Oxford 1982, pp. 429–453; Marcel van Ackeren: The Knowledge of the Good, Amsterdam 2003, pp. 262–267; Karl-Heinz Volkmann-Schluck: Plato. The Beginning of Metaphysics, Würzburg 1999, pp. 100–105; Lloyd P. Gerson: Knowing Persons, Oxford 2003, pp. 253–262; Verity Harte: The Philebus on Pleasure: The Good, the Bad and the False. In: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 104, 2004, pp. 113–130; Norman Mooradian: Converting Protarchus: Relativism and False Pleasures of Anticipation in Plato’s Philebus. In: Ancient Philosophy 16, 1996, pp. 93–112; Cynthia Hampton: Pleasure, Truth and Being in Plato’s Philebus: A reply to Professor Frede. In: Phronesis 32, 1987, pp. 253–262.
  67. ^ Maurizio Migliori: Man between Pleasure, Intelligence, and the Good, Milan 1993, pp. 330, 466 f., 486–499, 535–537; Giovanni Reale: Towards a New Interpretation of Plato, 2nd, expanded edition, Paderborn 2000, pp. 355–369, 413–444; Francisco L. Lisi: Good, Ethical Norm, and Pleasure in the Philebus. In: Méthexis 8, 1995, pp. 65–80, here: 76–79; Michael Hoffmann: The Emergence of Order, Stuttgart 1996, pp. 158–167; Georgia Mouroutsou: The Metaphor of Mixture in the Platonic Dialogues Sophist and Philebus, Sankt Augustin 2010, pp. 200 f., 231–234, 282; Enrico Berti: The Philebus and Plato's Unwritten Doctrines. In: Paolo Cosenza (Ed.): Plato's Philebus and Its Influence, Naples 1996, pp. 191–204. Cf. Gisela Striker: Peras und Apeiron, Göttingen 1970, pp. 45 f.
  68. ^ See Michael Erler: Plato, Basel 2007, pp. 259 (cautiously agreeing); Kenneth M. Sayre: Plato’s Late Ontology, 2nd, expanded edition, Las Vegas 2005, pp. 136–155 (agreeing; critically to Cynthia Hampton: Pleasure, Knowledge, and Being, Albany 1990, pp. 98–101); Dorothea Frede: Plato: Philebus. Translation and Commentary, Göttingen 1997, pp. 403–417 (skeptical); Eugenio E. Benitez: Forms in Plato’s Philebus, Assen 1989, p. 59 (rejecting); Georgia Mouroutsou: The Metaphor of Mixture in the Platonic Dialogues Sophist and Philebus, Sankt Augustin 2010, p. 282 (rejecting).
  69. ^ See Thomas M. Tuozzo: The General Account of Pleasure in Plato’s Philebus. In: Journal of the History of Philosophy 34, 1996, pp. 495–513.
  70. ^ Mark Moes: Plato’s Dialogue Form and the Care of the Soul, New York 2000, pp. 113–161.
  71. ^ See, for example, Franz Dirlmeier: Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics, 8th edition, Berlin 1983, p. 277, 499–501, 575 f. Cf. Dorothea Frede: Plato: Philebus. Translation and Commentary, Göttingen 1997, p. 418–426.
  72. ^ Theophrastus, Fragment 556, ed. by William W. Fortenbaugh et al.: Theophrastus of Eresus. Sources for his Life, Writings, Thought and Influence, Vol. 2, Leiden 1992, p. 380 f.
  73. ^ Dionysius of Halicarnassus, Demosthenes 23,4.
  74. ^ Diogenes Laertius 3,57 f.
  75. ^ Plato, Sophist 254b–255e.
  76. ^ See Heinrich Dörrie, Matthias Baltes: Platonism in Antiquity, Vol. 4, Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt 1996, p. 106–109, 372; Gerd Van Riel (ed.): Damascius: Commentary on Plato's Philebus, Paris 2008, p. XII–XVII. Cf. generally on Plutarch's Philebus reception Renato Laurenti: The Philebus in Plutarch. In: Paolo Cosenza (ed.): Plato's Philebus and its Legacy, Naples 1996, p. 53–71.
  77. ^ Heinrich Dörrie, Matthias Baltes: Platonism in Antiquity, Vol. 3, Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt 1993, p. 198.
  78. ^ Porphyry, Life of Plotinus 20,41–43.
  79. ^ Heinrich Dörrie, Matthias Baltes: Platonism in Antiquity, Vol. 3, Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt 1993, p. 198 and note 8.
  80. ^ An overview is provided by Dominic O’Meara: Neoplatonic Readings of the Philebus by Plato. In: Monique Dixsaut (ed.): The Fracture of Pleasure, Vol. 2, Paris 1999, p. 191–201. Cf. Gerd Van Riel (ed.): Damascius: Commentary on Plato's Philebus, Paris 2008, p. XXXII–LXVIII.
  81. ^ See Gerd Van Riel (ed.): Damascius: Commentary on Plato's Philebus, Paris 2008, p. XVII–XXV, LXXXVIII–CI and references to relevant passages at Pierre Hadot: Plotinus: Treatise 38, Paris 1988, p. 141–163, 169 f.; cf. at Hadot p. 24 f., 29, 299 f., 311–324, 330 f., 334–336.
  82. ^ Prolegomena to the Philosophy of Plato 26, ed. by Leendert Gerrit Westerink: Prolegomena to the Philosophy of Plato, Paris 1990, p. 39.
  83. ^ John M. Dillon (ed.): Iamblichus of Chalcis' Commentary on Plato's Dialogues, Fragments, Leiden 1973, p. 100–105; cf. p. 257–263.
  84. ^ Damascius, Life of Isidorus 42.
  85. ^ Gerd Van Riel (ed.): Damascius: Commentary on the Philebus by Plato, Paris 2008, p. I f., CXXX–CLXVIII, CLXXVI–CLXXIX. Cf. on the Neoplatonic commentary on Philebus Heinrich Dörrie, Matthias Baltes: Platonism in Antiquity, Vol. 3, Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt 1993, p. 198 f.
  86. ^ See Ernesto Berti: Philological Observations on Marsilio Ficino’s Version of the Philebus. In: Paolo Cosenza (ed.): Plato’s Philebus and Its Fate, Naples 1996, pp. 93–171 and his commentary introduction by the editor Michael J. B. Allen: Marsilio Ficino: The Philebus Commentary, Berkeley 1975, pp. 1–22.
  87. ^ See Hermann Krings: Genesis and Matter. In: Hartmut Buchner (ed.): F. W. J. Schelling: “Timaeus” (1794), Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt 1994, pp. 115–155, here: 117–120, 123, 127 f., 140–142, 145; Michael Franz: Schelling’s Tübingen Plato Studies, Göttingen 1996, pp. 258 f., 269–276, 279.
  88. ^ Pierre Garniron, Walter Jaeschke (eds.): Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: Lectures on the History of Philosophy, Part 3, Hamburg 1996, pp. 30 f.
  89. ^ Friedrich Schleiermacher: Philebus. Introduction. In: Friedrich Daniel Ernst Schleiermacher: On the Philosophy of Plato, edited by Peter M. Steiner, Hamburg 1996, pp. 303–312, here: 311 f.
  90. ^ Ulrich von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff: Plato. His Life and Works, 5th edition, Berlin 1959 (1st edition Berlin 1919), pp. 497 f.
  91. ^ Lecture notes in: Friedrich Nietzsche: Works. Critical Complete Edition, Division 2, Vol. 4, Berlin 1995, p. 139.
  92. ^ Paul Friedländer: Plato, Vol. 3, 3rd, revised edition, Berlin 1975, pp. 286 f.
  93. ^ Paul Natorp: Plato’s Theory of Ideas, Hamburg 1994 (text of the 2nd edition of 1921), pp. 312–349, here: 313.
  94. ^ Paul Natorp: Plato’s Theory of Ideas, Hamburg 1994 (text of the 2nd edition of 1921), pp. 343–345.
  95. ^ Hans-Georg Gadamer: Plato’s Dialectical Ethics. In: Gadamer: Collected Works, Vol. 5, Tübingen 1985 (first published 1931), pp. 3–163.
  96. ^ Robert J. Dostal: Gadamer’s Platonism and the Philebus: The Significance of the Philebus for Gadamer’s Thought. In: Christopher Gill, François Renaud (eds.): Hermeneutic Philosophy and Plato. Gadamer’s Response to the Philebus, Sankt Augustin 2010, pp. 23–39, here: 27, 29–33.
  97. ^ Hans-Georg Gadamer: Plato’s Dialectical Ethics. In: Gadamer: Collected Works, Vol. 5, Tübingen 1985 (first published 1931), pp. 3–163, here: 118.
  98. ^ Walter Mesch: False Pleasure as Baseless Hope. Gadamer and the Recent Philebus Interpretation. In: Christopher Gill, François Renaud (eds.): Hermeneutic Philosophy and Plato. Gadamer’s Response to the Philebus, Sankt Augustin 2010, pp. 121–137, here: 131 f.
  99. ^ See to Gadamer’s Philebus reception the contributions in the collection of essays edited by Christopher Gill and François Renaud: Hermeneutic Philosophy and Plato. Gadamer’s Response to the Philebus, Sankt Augustin 2010 (overview in the introduction by the editors pp. 9–20).
  100. ^ Herbert Marcuse: On the Critique of Hedonism. In: Herbert Marcuse: Writings, Vol. 3, Frankfurt am Main 1979, pp. 263–265.
  101. ^ Donald Davidson: Plato’s Philebus, New York/London 1990 (text of the dissertation with a new introduction), Preface and pp. 13 f. of the introduction.
  102. ^ Plato, Philebus 38e–39e. Jacques Derrida: Dissemination, Vienna 1995 (German translation of the original edition of 1972), pp. 193 ff.

Further reading[edit]

External links[edit]

Leave a Reply